Humanities' Computings

paper
Authorship
  1. 1. Meurig Beynon

    Computer Science - University of Warwick

  2. 2. Roderick R. Klein

    Syscom Lab - University of Savoie

  3. 3. Steve Russ

    Computer Science - University of Warwick

Work text
This plain text was ingested for the purpose of full-text search, not to preserve original formatting or readability. For the most complete copy, refer to the original conference program.

As discussed by McCarty, Beynon and Russ in a session organised at ACH/ALLC 2005, there is a remarkable convergence between McCarty’s concept of ‘model-building in the role of experimental end-maker’
(McCarty 2005:15) - a cornerstone in his vision for
humanities computing (HC) - and the principles of
Empirical Modelling (EM) (EMweb). More problematic is the tension between the pluralist conception of computing that is an essential ingredient of McCarty’s stance on HC, and the prominent emphasis on ‘dissolving dualities’ in McCarty, Beynon and Russ (ACH/ALLC 2005:138). Resolving this tension transforms the status of HC from one amongst many varieties of computing to that of first amongst equals.
The plurality of computing In presenting his “rationale for a computing practice that is of and foras well as in the humanities”, McCarty (2005:14) emphasises the plurality of computing. Following Mahoney (2005), he calls into question the search for “the essential nature of
computing” and appeals to history as evidence that ‘what people want computers to do’ and ‘how people
design computers to do it’ determine many different
computings. The audacity of McCarty’s vision in
recommending his readers, as would-be practitioners of a variety of computing, to “[turn] their attention from working out principles to pursuing practice”, is striking.
It is hard to imagine a reputable computer science
department encouraging its students to see computing
primarily in terms of its practice - congenial to the
students themselves as this might be. In promoting
computing as an academic subject, there is no recognised focus for developing ‘scientific’ principles other than the theory of computation at its historical core (Turing).
McCarty instead sets out to characterise the practice of HC in such terms that it has its own integrity.
When contemplating McCarty’s boldness, it is instructive
to consider the alternatives. The problematic nature
of the relationship between computer science and the
humanities is notorious. Consider, for instance, Chesher’s observation (ACH/ALLC 2005:39) that - in teaching a course in Arts Informatics: “The Humanities critiques of science and technology (Heidegger, Virilio, Coyne)
are difficult to reconcile with scientific conceptions of humanities practices (Holtzman). Each of these areas
places quite different, and often clearly conflicting
discourses, techniques and systems of value”. From
this perspective, seeking to characterise HC as a unified entity seems to be the only plausible strategy, though it resembles conjuring a stable compound from an explosive
combination of improbable ingredients. Invoking
EM is helpful in critiquing McCarty’s treatment of this unification (2005: 195-8). To elaborate the chemistry metaphor, it illuminates the precise nature of the reaction and identifies it with a more general phenomenon.
How modelling and computer science interact in
humanities computing The semantic orientation of HC is crucial to understanding its chemistry. Where computer
science emphasises prescribing and representing precise
intended meanings, humanities is of its essence obliged to engage with meanings that are ambiguous and unintended.
The authentic spirit of McCarty’s notion of HC is
captured in Ramsay’s ‘placing visualisation in a rhetorical
context’ (in his presentation at ACH/ALLC 2005:200) - the creative construction of an artefact as a subject for personal experience, whose interpretation is to be
negotiated and potentially shared. This theme is amplified
in many topical contributions to the proceedings of ACH/ALLC 20051.
Interpreting such activities from an EM perspective obliges a more prominent shift in emphasis from the accepted view of computing than is acknowledged in (McCarty,
2005) - the rich diversity of HC activities cannot be
attributed primarily to the versatility of the Turing Machine
as a generator of functional relationships2. In EM, the focus is upon the role that observables, dependency
and agency play in the modelling activity, and each of these concepts appeals to a personal experience of
interaction with technology that defies merely functional
characterisation. On this basis, EM trades first and
foremost not in objective ‘formal’ interpretations, but
in speculative constructions that cannot be realised
or mediated without skillful and intelligent human
interaction. Appreciation of observables, dependency relationships and potential agency is acquired through developing familiarity and evolving skills. This is in
keeping with Polanyi’s account - cited by McCarty (2005:44) - of how awareness is transformed through skill acquisition. Functional abstraction can express transcendental computational relationships, but does not encompass such issues, which relate to what is given to the human interpreter in their immediate experience.
A useful parallel may be drawn with musical
performance. Though one and the same functional
relationship between visual stimulus and tactile response is involved, a virtuoso pianist can perform an extended extract from a complex score in the time it takes a novice to identify the initial chord.
In this context, it is significant that - in elaborating his vision for HC, McCarty (2005:53) drew upon his
experience of making a specific model - the Onomasticon
for Ovid’s Metamorphoses - whose construction and
interpretation can be viewed as an EM archetype.
Model-building in the Onomasticon, being based on spreadsheet principles, supplies the framework within which McCarty’s experimental ‘end-maker’ role can be played out most effectively. It is implausible that the same qualities can be realised on account of adopting
other model-building principles, such as the use of
object-orientation, since - in conventional use - their
primary purpose is to rationalise the specification of
complex functional abstractions. This challenges Galey’s - no doubt pragmatically most sensible! - contention (ACH/ALLC 2005:198) that “In order to bring electronic editing projects like the eNVS to the screen, humanists must think past documents to embrace the principles of object-oriented and standards-compliant programming and design.”.
Humanities computing as the archetype for all varieties of computing Though McCarty (2005:14) first discusses
plurality in computing in relation to communities of
practice quite generally, his interest in a conceptual unification of HC and computer science (2005:195-8)
acknowledges the plurality of HC itself. Where
McCarty (2005:198) identifies “general-purpose modelling software, such as a spreadsheet or database” as one component within a more diverse unity, Beynon
and Russ have a radically different conceptualisation
in mind. Their account identifies EM as hybrid part-
automated-part-human processing within a framework for generalised computation similar to that implicit in McCarty’s Onomasticon3. Within this framework, the functionality of the Turing Machine is subsumed by
closely prescribed and highly automated modes of
interaction, whilst modelling with the Onomasticon is a more open-ended human-centred form of processing
- though by no means the most general activity of this
nature. This places EM at the centre of a broader pragmatic
discourse on programming that complements the
conventional rational discourse (Beynon, Boyatt and Russ, 2005).
The emphasis in (McCarty, Beynon and Russ, 2005)
on dissolving dualities within the frame of Radical
Empiricism (James, 1996) may still appear to be
mismatched to the plurality of HC. Klein’s reaction to EM exemplifies the issues. In seeking a technology to support a world-wide collaborative creative venture4, he recognises the qualities of EM as supporting a concept
of creativity that is expressed in the motto: “Build
the camera while shooting the film” (cf. Lubart 1996,
Klein 2002, METISweb). For Klein, this recognition
calls to mind Joas’s concept of creative action, and the processes that shape the evolving meaning of context
in Lévy’s ‘universe in perpetual creation’ (1997). The
relevance of Radical Empiricism even where such
diverse perspectives are being invoked stems from the subject-independent association it establishes between sense-making and the classification of relationships between experiences. For instance, whatever meaningful relationships inform the semiotics of Lévy’s Information
Economy Meta Language (2005) should somewhere
be ‘experiencable’ (cf. James, 1996:160), and in this manner be amenable to EM. Seen in this light, Radical Empiricism and EM relate to universal learning activities
that are orthogonal to the subject of the learning (cf.
Beynon and Roe, 2004). This accords with James’s
monist view of experience and pluralist view of
understanding (James, 1996:194). It is also resonates best with cultures where understanding through relationship has higher priority than objectification. In emphasising interaction and the interpretation of relationships, EM does not prescribe a rigid frame for understanding, but exhibits that positive quality of blandness5 (Jullien, 2004) that affords participation in many relationships. Even within the small community of EM practitioners,
this potential for plurality can be seen in different nuances
and idioms of elaboration, as in relation to analogue,
phenomenological or ecological variants of computing.
The aspiration of EM to connect computing decisively with modelling was also that of object-oriented (OO) modelling, as first conceived nearly forty years ago
(Birtwistle, Dahl, Myhrhaug and Nygaard, 1982). As a young technology, EM cannot yet compete with OO in tackling technical challenges in HC, such as devising adaptive web interfaces for the ‘end-maker’. Perhaps, unlike OO, it can be more widely adopted and developed
without in the process being conscripted to the cause of supporting functional abstraction. If so, it may yet
demonstrate that the modelling activity McCarty has identified as characteristic of HC is in fact an integral and fundamental part of every computing practice: that all computings are humanities’ computings.
Notes
1. For instance: acknowledging that there is no definitive digital representation (Galey, ACH/ALLC 2005:198); recognising the essential need for interactive playful
visualisation (Ramsay, ibid: 200; Wolff, ibid: 273;
Durnad and Wardrip-Fruin, ibid: 61); and appreciating
the importance of collaborative modelling and role
integration (Best et al, ibid: 13; van Zundert and
Dalen-Oskam, ibid: 249).
2. For more background, see McCarty (2005) Figure 4.2 and the associated discussion on pages 195-8.
3. The framework alluded to here is that of the Abstract Definitive Machine, as described at (EMweb).
4. The Metis project (METISweb) is exploring collective
creativity of global virtual teams of students and
professionals in the movie industry.
5. The Chinese ‘dan’, which Jullien translates as ‘fadeur’: Varsano notes that she “would have liked to find an English word that signifies a lack of flavor and that at the same time benefits from the positive connotations
supplied by a culture that honors the presence of
absence” (see Schroeder 2005). References
ACH/ALLC 2005: Conference Abstracts. University of Victoria, BC, Canada, June 2005
Beynon, W.M. (2005) Radical Empiricism, Empirical Modelling and the nature of knowing, Cognitive
Technologies and the Pragmatics of Cognition,
Pragmatics and Cognition, 13:3, 615-646
Beynon, W.M. and Roe, C.P. (2004) Computer Support for Constructionism in Context, in Proc ICALT 04, Joensuu, Finland, August 2004, 216-220
Beynon W.M., Boyatt R.C., Russ S.B. (2005)
Rethinking Programming, In Proc. ITNG 2006, Las Vegas, April 2006 (to appear)
Birtwistle, G M, Dahl, O-J, Myhrhaug, B, Nygaard, K. (1982) Simula Begin (2nd ed.), Studentlitteratur, Lund, Sweden, 1982
Coyne, R. (1999) Technoromanticism, Digital narrative, holism, and the romance of the real. Cambridge, Mass: MIT Press, 1999
Heidegger, M. (1977) The question concerning technology, and other essays. New York: Garland Pub.
Holtzman, S.R. (1994) Digital Mantras. The languages of abstract and virtual worlds. Cambridge Mass. & London: MIT Press
Joas, H. (1996) The Creativity of Action, Blackwell
Publishers (UK)
James, W. (1996) Essays in Radical Empiricism (first published 1912), New York: Dover
Jullien, F. (2004) In Praise of Blandness: Proceeding from Chinese Thought and Aesthetics, trans. By Paula M. Varsano, Cambridge, MA: MIT Press
Klein, R.R. (2002) ‘La Mètis-pour-créer ? ’Vers l’Analyse
Médiologique d’une Métaphore: La Créativité
Selon la lecture de l’ouvrage de François JULLIEN
(1989) : Procès ou Création. Memoire de MSc
Communications. Université de Nice-Sophia-Antipolis, France, 223pp
Lévy, P. (1997) Cyberculture: rapport au Conseil de l’Europe ed. Odile Jacob, Paris
Lévy, P. Cognitive Augmentation Languages for
Collective Intelligence and Human Development. http://www.icml9.org/program/public/documents/LEVY-CRICS-205153.pdf (accessed 14/11/2005)
Lubart, T.I. (1996) Creativity across cultures, Handbook of creativity (R.J.Sternberg ed.), Cambridge Press.
Mahoney, M.S. (2005) The Histories of Computing(s), Interdisciplinary Science Review, 30(2), June 2005, 119-135
McCarty, W. (2005) Humanities Computing,
Basingstoke: Palgrave Macmillan
McCarty, W, Beynon, W.M. and Russ, S.B. (2005) Human Computing: Modelling with Meaning, in ACH+ALLC 2005, 138-144
Schroeder, S. (2005) Book Review of In Praise of
Blandness: Proceeding from Chinese Thought and Aesthetics, François Jullien. Translated by Paula M. Varsano., Essays in Philosophy, Vol. 6, No. 1,
January 2005
Turing, A.M. (1936) On computable real numbers, with an application to the Entscheidung problems,
Proc. London Math. Soc., 42, 230-265.
Virilio, P. (1991) Lost Dimension, New York: Semiotext(e) (Autonomedia)
EMweb. http://www.dcs.warwick.ac.uk/modelling/
(accessed 14/11/2005)
METISweb. http://www.metis-global.org (accessed 14/11/2005)

If this content appears in violation of your intellectual property rights, or you see errors or omissions, please reach out to Scott B. Weingart to discuss removing or amending the materials.

Conference Info

Complete

ACH/ALLC / ACH/ICCH / ADHO / ALLC/EADH - 2006

Hosted at Université Paris-Sorbonne, Paris IV (Paris-Sorbonne University)

Paris, France

July 5, 2006 - July 9, 2006

151 works by 245 authors indexed

The effort to establish ADHO began in Tuebingen, at the ALLC/ACH conference in 2002: a Steering Committee was appointed at the ALLC/ACH meeting in 2004, in Gothenburg, Sweden. At the 2005 meeting in Victoria, the executive committees of the ACH and ALLC approved the governance and conference protocols and nominated their first representatives to the ‘official’ ADHO Steering Committee and various ADHO standing committees. The 2006 conference was the first Digital Humanities conference.

Conference website: http://www.allc-ach2006.colloques.paris-sorbonne.fr/

Series: ACH/ICCH (26), ACH/ALLC (18), ALLC/EADH (33), ADHO (1)

Organizers: ACH, ADHO, ALLC

Tags
  • Keywords: None
  • Language: English
  • Topics: None